Skip to main content

Guidelines for conscientious objection in Spain: a proposal involving prerequisites and protocolized procedure

Abstract

Healthcare professionals often face ethical conflicts and challenges related to decision-making that have necessitated consideration of the use of conscientious objection (CO). No current guidelines exist within Spain’s healthcare system regarding acceptable rationales for CO, the appropriate application of CO, or practical means to support healthcare professionals who wish to become conscientious objectors. As such, a procedural framework is needed that not only assures the appropriate use of CO by healthcare professionals but also demonstrates its ethical validity, legislative compliance through protection of moral freedoms and patients’ rights to receive health care. Our proposal consists of prerequisites of eligibility for CO (individual reference, specific clinical context, ethical justification, assurance of non-discrimination, professional consistency, attitude of mutual respect, assurance of patient rights and safety) and a procedural process (notification and preparation, documentation and confidentiality, evaluation of prerequisites, non-abandonment, transparency, allowance for unforeseen objection, compensatory responsibilities, access to guidance and/or consultative advice, and organizational guarantee of professional substitution). We illustrate the real-world utility of the proposed framework through a case discussion in which our guidelines are applied.

Introduction

Definition of conscientious objection

Conscientious objection (CO) is the refusal to perform acts or services on ethical or religious grounds [1]. Therefore, in medicine CO occurs when a healthcare worker refuses to fulfill a professional duty required by law, regulations, institutional protocols, and/or court orders, citing a conflict with personal values, ideas, and/or beliefs [2,3,4,5,6,7,8,9,10,11]. In CO, the objector acknowledges the requirement imposed by the authority (and that this obligation is binding) but believes that his or her individual values should prevail in the specific case presented [11].

Unlike other forms of dissent, the conscientious objector does not seek to change the rules and regulations per se but rather desires exemption from performing a specific act that contradicts his or her conscience [5]. In contrast, civil disobedience [7, 12,13,14] denotes non-compliance with an established law considered unjust, the ultimate goal of which is to remove or change the norm itself. If this non-compliance defies an active court order, the disputant is termed an “objector” [8]. In other words, CO describes dissent on an individual level, whereas civil disobedience, often occurring within the political sphere, addresses dissent on a collective basis [7].

While universal agreement of the need for CO is lacking, the use CO, in a plural society, is gaining acceptance among healthcare professionals in recent decades as an ethical and legal right [4]. However, others counter this view, holding that all medical professionals must act in accordance with professional duty and societal obligations of medicine that supersede personal moral convictions [4, 9, 15,16,17,18].

Regulatory framework regarding conscientious objection in Spain

In Spain, CO was claimed at the beginning by men who were called for military service. On the other hand, in the use of CO in health care began in 1985, when abortion was decriminalized [19, 20]. Since that time, steadily increasing complexity of clinical practice [2] and technological advancements have generated interest in applying CO to a broader range of clinical situations, such as the limitation of therapeutic efforts, facilitated palliation during end-of-life care, rejection of life-sustaining therapies by patients, proper handling of human embryos and stem cells and others. As a result, CO in Spain is gaining acceptance among healthcare professionals as an ethical and legal right. Especially since a specific law regulating euthanasia and medically assisted suicide was passed in 2021 [21].

Article 16.1 of the Spanish Constitution [22] establishes ideological and religious freedom as a Fundamental Right. Ruling 15/1982 [23] of the Constitutional Court recognized that CO “is a right explicitly and implicitly existing in the Spanish constitutional order” and, therefore, the exercise of individual freedom for ethical reasons should be exercised in private and professional realms. In another ruling, the Constitutional Court (53/1985) [20] stated that the right to CO need not be specifically regulated, because it is implicit to Article 16.1 of the Spanish Constitution. Later rulings by the Constitutional Court, however, qualified the thesis that CO is not a general right, only exempting an individual from fulfilling legal duties in exceptional situations [24, 25].

From a legislative standpoint, CO is regulated in two Spanish laws: national law that governs CO for healthcare workers is in the Spanish Public Act 2/2010 on Sexual and Reproductive Health and Voluntary Interruption of Pregnancy [26] and Organic Law 3/2021 for the Regulation of Euthanasia [21]. On the other hand, several regional governments in Spain include CO in legislation pertaining to advance directives: Madrid, Valencia, Extremadura, the Balearic Islands, Murcia and La Rioja [2, 27] (see Table 1).

Table 1 Spanish legislation and regulations on CO

Professional societies of various disciplines support the ethical justification of CO in their regulatory codes of conduct. Article 34.2 of the Spanish Medical Ethics Code (2022) [6] describes minimum requirements of CO and highlights CO as an essential prerequisite in order to guarantee freedom and independence in their professional practice.” Similarly, the Code of Ethics for Nursing (1989) [28] and the Code of Ethics for the Pharmaceutical Profession (2018) [29] support and regulate the use of CO. These various ethical codes support the notion that CO is a right of all medical professionals that must be exercised individually and with prior justification. Furthermore, the use of CO should not incur benefit or harm to those who exercise this right.

The purpose of this document

Various ethical and legal factors make the current process of creating a proper CO challenging and raise the question of whether a set of guidelines may be useful. In this document, we first explain the difficulties faced by those considering CO and detail several pro and con arguments regarding the value of guidelines for CO. We then offer a justification in favour of such guidelines and propose a framework and recommendations (a guideline) to help health professionals and governance bodies to enact COs in an effective and ethically and legally acceptable manner. Finally, we present a clinical case demonstrating the context for the use of CO and apply our guideline to the clinical case to demonstrate its utility.

Are guidelines for conscientious objection necessary?

The complexity of the problem

Proper use of CO requires careful consideration of associated ethical, clinical, and legal issues and implications. First, clinicians may offer numerous reasons for objection, many of which are not strictly moral in nature and therefore not ethically justified (see Table 2). Professionals may claim status as conscientious objectors, but adduced reasons lack merit, such as when motives for non-conformist positions belie true moral conflict [8, 19]. Given that objections can be marked by both rational and irrational responses to events and situations, determination of the validity of such objections is not straightforward.

Table 2 Examples of grounds stated by health care professionals for exercising CO

Second, effective use of CO requires careful consideration of ethical and legal nuances of objection. Some examples: What specific ethical values and/or principles validate COs? Can administrative bodies, such as a group medical practice, also invoke CO or are COs restricted to individual persons? How should COs be communicated to the institution and to the patient? What details in care delivery must be addressed after objections are instituted? What part do local, regional, and national laws play regarding CO? These and other questions lay at the heart of a judiciously applied CO.

Given this complexity, a procedural framework is needed that not only assures the appropriate use of CO by healthcare professionals but also demonstrates its ethical validity and legislative compliance through protection of moral freedoms and patients’ rights to receive health care.

What is a guideline for CO?

Guidelines in clinical ethics are recommendations and/or standards based on established ethical principles that healthcare agents can use to make ultimate decisions regarding care [43]. Such guidelines serve as regulatory safeguards against conflict-generating situations frequently encountered in clinical practice and provide guidance.

In practice, guidelines offer best available options for proper decision-making, delineate particular steps to follow, and identify responsible agents [44]. For instance, guidelines on Jehovah Witnesses and Refusal of Treatment clarify particular cases in which use of transfusions is permitted and specify responsibilities of each involved party (i.e., physician, patient, family member, legal counsel, etc.) [45, 46]. Clinicians review guideline recommendations and apply them to the specific case in question as they feel appropriate (without obligation), though many institutions often expect explanations in cases where clinical decisions deviate from the guideline recommendations [47].

Making the case for guidelines in CO

When approaching cases involving CO, it is helpful to have a clear process that permits medical professionals to support individually held values without compromising overall healthcare delivery [15, 48] and takes into account the complex clinical, ethical and legal aspects cited above. Guidelines offer a structure by which clinicians can navigate complex situations for which prior training and experience may be minimal.

The use of guidelines has some disadvantages. First, practitioners may encounter difficulty when applying general guidelines to any individual case, as clinical details may differ between cases, and legal standards may vary between municipalities. Overzealous application of standards may lead to inadvertent biases such as overconfidence, availability bias, and premature closure that can detract from appropriate use of CO in individual cases. Second, guidelines may lack necessary robustness if requested COs are infrequent in clinical practice. For example, institutions may not possess the means to create specific guidelines on CO without sufficient data to support their development. Third, dissemination and updating of guidelines may not be equal or adequate across all institutions, ultimately limiting their scope and application unless an institution-wide commitment exists. In this regard, Clinical Ethics Committees may take a leading role. Finally, CO guidelines provide assistance in ethically based decision-making but not legal protection per se. Other legislative and institutional mechanisms are required to address the direct legal implications.

Despite these concerns, we feel that creation of a set of guidelines is possible and necessary. Properly devised guidelines can support individually held values of medical professionals while simultaneously protecting, distributing, and mediating accepted standards of overall healthcare delivery, particularly with the help of Clinical Ethics Committees, present in most healthcare institutions in Spain.

Guidelines for the appropriate use of conscientious objection in Spain

No current guidelines exist within Spain’s healthcare system regarding acceptable rationales for CO, the appropriate application of CO, or practical means to support healthcare professionals who wish to ask for objection in some specific cases. As no current methodology exists that would reconcile these opposing positions, we propose a novel evaluative and procedural framework that would facilitate appropriate use of CO by Spanish healthcare professionals who wish request conscientious objection is provided by a specific situation.

Our proposal is a set of recommendations that are designed to reconcile current regulations in Spain with several potentially conflicting ethical and societal values (i.e. the protection of freedom of the professional and the provision of equitable healthcare delivery). The following recommendations (see Table 3) aim to ensure that the CO is ethically and legally acceptable.

Table 3 Guideline for CO: eligibility prerequisites and procedural process

Eligibility prerequisites for CO

For adequate CO, all of the following prerequisites should be present, and performed as follows.

To be performed by the requesting professional and/or governing institution:

  1. 1)

    Individual Reference. CO must be exercised on an individual [7, 49], rather than collective (i.e., an act involving civil disobedience) basis. Collective objection in medicine is not valid [6, 11, 29] because CO-based stances are necessarily particular to the individual and represent acts of personal moral reflection unbiased by coercion or pressure from peers, service obligations, or institutional politics [50]. In some cases, private institutions with specific values are against any medical procedure. In those cases, the Institution will not offer that specific procedure to their patients [4].

  2. 2)

    Specific Clinical Context. CO must apply to specific a clinical situation in a non-binding manner with regard to past (and potential future) situations. CO starts and ends with the specific clinical situation to which objection is raised. Furthermore, medical professionals should exercise CO without being influenced by decisions made in the past [2, 11]. The professional may revoke status as an objector at any point at which the specific situation no longer leads to a true internal and moral conflict.

  3. 3)

    Ethical Justification. CO must arise from the professional’s internal convictions, thereby evincing the ethical tenet of autonomy through the exercise of individual freedom. Furthermore, the values questioned by the norm must be essential to the professional [11, 14]. For example, CO is not admissible if the procedure is illegal; if the technic requested is outside medical practice or the physician is not competent in this area; if inertia, opportunism, or ease [6, 11, 18, 29] are underlying drivers of the objection. In order to clarify ethical validity, some have suggested that a committee must formally evaluate the declared grounds in each case [48] to validate the existence of true moral conflicts for the professional and to verify that no secondary benefits are sought [11, 17]. Others have advocated for a formal evaluative process conducted by professional associations to help medical professionals differentiate appropriate CO cases from those in which moral conflict of individual conscience does not, in fact, exist [14].

  4. 4)

    Assurance of Non-discrimination. CO is inadmissible if discriminatory or prejudicial motivations for the CO are present [6, 29]. For example, one cannot object to caring for a patient due to his or her ethnicity, race, belief, or ideology [51]. Rather, COs must originate solely from genuine ethical conflicts intrinsic to the specific, requested procedure, irrespective of personal characteristics of the patient or other factors.

  5. 5)

    Professional Consistency. The exercise of CO must maintain cohesion of purpose and behaviour across different spheres of application [7]. For example, one cannot object to an action for patients in the public health sector but perform the action for patients in the private sector [14]. Since CO derives from internal moral conflicts and not external circumstances, CO should apply equally to patients regardless of context.

To be performed by the requesting professional and by the governing institution of the professional:

  1. 6)

    Attitude of Mutual Respect. Throughout the process of CO, all parties must maintain respect to one another. Medical professionals should continue demonstrating respect towards patients, co-workers, and authorities and their respective values and decisions.xl Specifically, the professional should avoid imposition of his or her beliefs upon others and/or making value judgments [29, 52]. On the other hand, the objecting professional must also be respected by other professionals, such that he or she not suffer psychological, occupational, or other consequences as a result of being an objector [48, 53]. Similarly, in situations in which the majority of co-workers elects CO, protection of the non-objecting professional from discrimination and/or other harms is equally important.

  2. 7)

    Assurance of Patient Rights and Safety. The rights of patients to make decisions and to request and receive care must be always honoured, regardless of whether or not the professional is an objector [4, 10, 54]. Physicians must inform the patient about the procedure and how to access it, even if the physician is an objector to this specific technique [4, 55]. Physicians may object, but they may not hinder the patient’s access to health care [4]. In other words, if CO indirectly or directly causes patients to risk abandonment, neglect, and/or harm, such as when professional substitution cannot be assured to receive the requested service, the CO is not admissible [15, 33]. As long as the requested service accords with accepted standards of medical quality and safety, a necessary predication for any requested therapy, the potential for patient neglect and compromise of established care standards can both be averted.

Procedural process

For adequate CO, the following procedure should be followed as indicated below.

To be performed by the requesting professional and approved by the governing institution of the professional through internal institutional processes:

  1. 1)

    Notification and Preparation. Requests for CO must occur with sufficient advance notice to prepare suitable arrangements for all parties and minimize unexpected problems [5]. The declaration in question must be made to the head of the service or hospital unit, who, in turn, must organize and strategize the care of users potentially affected by the CO [6, 10, 18].

  2. 2)

    Documentation and Confidentiality. CO must be formally requested in writing to the service chief at which the medical professional is employed [7] and to corresponding professional association(s) as required [6]. Confidentiality of conscientious objector status should be strictly maintained by governance bodies (i.e. work unit and/or institutional administration), with appropriate details shared only as necessary to ensure proper arrangements are made [29].

  3. 3)

    Evaluation of Prerequisites. Both the medical professional seeking CO and supervising and/or governing bodies should evaluate the request for CO with a diligent review of the prerequisites noted above [18].

  4. 4)

    Non-abandonment. The professional must carry out all other procedures, whether prior or subsequent, that are not governed by the CO, as patient care requires [4, 18, 26, 53].

  5. 5)

    Transparency. In order to safeguard clinical relationships and trust with patients, the medical professional must explain to the patient, and, where appropriate, to the patient’s relatives, his or her status as an objector [6] and state that (s)he will therefore be attended by a different professional with the same quality standards [4, 10, 32].

  6. 6)

    Allowance for Unforeseen Objection: CO may be accepted in certain cases with accelerated timeframes without advance notice or preparation only as exceptions on a case-by-case basis [6, 56]. One example in Spain involved emergency medical professionals who refused to comply with the rule to care for patients without legal residency on the grounds that such individuals lacked healthcare benefits for which only patients with legal residency were entitled [12]. In such circumstances, the CO must still be reported post hoc in order to comply with the aforementioned requirements [57].

  7. 7)

    Compensatory Responsibilities: The medical professional claiming CO exemption from certain work-based actions is subject to other occupational responsibilities in their stead [8]. In other words, CO cannot lead to any primary or secondary gain for the objecting professional [6, 29].

  8. 8)

    Access to Guidance and/or Consultative Advice: If there are any doubts or problems related to the CO claim or process itself, professionals should request guidance and advice from their respective professional associations and/or the corresponding Clinical Ethics Committee (CEC) [6, 28] as available.

To be performed by the governing institution of the professional:

  1. 9)

    Organizational Guarantee of Professional Substitution. To guarantee continuity of care [2, 58], the work unit and institution must make reasonable steps to ensure that care by professional substitutes who assume clinical responsibilities from the objecting professional will not result in any detrimental consequences to the patient [7, 54]. This requirement for parity of care standards also applies in cases where the patient must be referred to another facility to continue care [7, 54].

Application of the guideline to a clinical scenario

Clinical scenario

Pedro is a 58-year-old man diagnosed seven years prior with amyotrophic lateral sclerosis (ALS), a progressive, degenerative neurologic condition that has now rendered him highly dependent in basic activities of everyday life. Three weeks ago, he was admitted to intensive care unit of the local hospital for respiratory failure requiring life-supportive therapy (including endotracheal intubation and invasive mechanical ventilation) with three other similar hospitalizations in the prior six months for the same condition. Several days ago, Pedro was transferred to the pulmonary medicine ward after agreeing to receive a tracheostomy for a projected course of prolonged, ventilator-based support. Several days later, Pedro requests discontinuation of invasive mechanical ventilation and all additional means of life support, stating that he no longer wants to be “connected to a machine” or dependent upon a mechanical ventilator. In addition, he requests euthanasia. Having discussed the matter with his wife and sons, who understand his decision. His psychiatrist has also determined that Pedro is fully capable of making decisions. However, Pedro’s attending physician disagrees, as she believes strongly that preservation of life is an inviolable value. As a result, a moral conflict arises, which she is unsure how to resolve, and she considers using CO to avoid having to comply with patient’s request. How should she and her supervisors proceed?

In the case presented above, Pedro’s request euthanasia involves a moral conflict for the medical practitioner, who thus considers CO. Our recommended framework serves as a guide to both the medical professional and supervising administrators in determining legitimacy of the request and best strategy to execute, as follows:

Eligibility prerequisites of the CO request

While the majority of the prerequisites was satisfied by the written request of the objecting pulmonologist, all required independent verification by the institution:

  1. 1)

    Individual Reference. In the clinical scenario presented, the professional’s moral and ethical quandary applied CO as an individual only and not as a collective body.

  2. 2)

    Specific Clinical Context. The CO in this case applied to the specific clinical situation of in case of requesting euthanasia or medical aid to suicide.

  3. 3)

    Ethical Justification. The practitioner claimed non-maleficence as the ethical grounds for the CO, because she believed that preservation of life is an inviolable value. This was an accepted criterion, as it did not involve convenience, ease, or other disqualifying motives.

  4. 4)

    Assurance of Non-Discrimination. The physician did not object to performing other medical acts (apart from the specific act(s) that violate her ethics) pertaining to the care of Pedro, nor that other practitioners provide the requested service in her stead.

  5. 5)

    Professional Consistency. There were not enough data currently presented in the case to satisfy this criterion for CO eligibility. As such, the objecting professional must provide evidence to support the claim of consistency (to be verified later by the governing institution) or the governing institution must perform such a verification independently.

  6. 6)

    Attitude of Mutual respect. No value judgments were made by the requesting professional, substituting professional, or patient, neither in reference to the medical act in question nor the request for CO.

  7. 7)

    Assurance of Patient Rights and Safety. The governing institution must confirm that the patient can receive the health service by a substitute practitioner within a reasonable timeframe, as the request falls within accepted standards of clinical practice.

Procedural process of the CO request

The objecting professional and her department chief followed the procedural steps as follows:

  1. 1)

    Notification and Preparation. In this case, the pulmonologist promptly contacted her department chief in order to request CO after carefully reflecting upon Pedro’s request euthanasia and deciding that she was at a moral impasse in the matter.

  2. 2)

    Documentation and Confidentiality. The medical professional submitted a written request for CO to the department chief, which was then kept confidential, with only necessary information conveyed to others directly involved in the case in a manner that protected privacy.

  3. 3)

    Evaluation of Eligibility Prerequisites. The department chief verified with the pulmonologist that the eligibility prerequisites had been satisfied. As noted above, the governing entity marked as pending the following: 1) proof of consistency across various professional contexts activities and 2) assurance of a suitable substitute professional to provide the requested act within an acceptable timeframe.

  4. 4)

    Non-abandonment. The department chief confirmed that the pulmonologist would continue to care for Pedro apart from the act involving CO and made arrangements to identify a suitable professional to provide the requested medical act in a mutually acceptable timeframe.

  5. 5)

    Transparency. The objecting pulmonologist directly explained to Pedro her intention of being an objector and that arrangements for another professional with the same qualifications will be made for the requested act.

  6. 6)

    Professional Substitution. The department chief and institution reaffirmed that a reasonable professional alternate must be offered to the patient to provide the requested service. If this surrogate provider were not available, the CO would be annulled.

  7. 7)

    Allowance for Unforeseen objection. This criterion did not apply in this case as significant advance notice had been provided, and the act was not emergently necessary.

  8. 8)

    Compensatory responsibilities. The objecting professional and the governing institution agreed that once CO is enacted that other healthcare tasks will be assigned in lieu of the objected service.

  9. 9)

    Consultation. The department chief communicated with the medical professional that she is able to consult with her professional association or with the Clinical Ethics Committee of the hospital at any point regarding any aspect of this case and the use of CO.

Therefore, in this case scenario, all criteria have been satisfied except for two eligibility prerequisites (Professional Consistency and Assurance of Patient Rights and Safety) that must be completed prior to allowing the medical professional to abstain from euthanasia under protection of CO.

Conclusions

Healthcare professionals consider the use of CO when ethical values conflict with a requested healthcare act. When requested by medical professionals, COs should not negatively impact any party – the medical professional, institution, or patient in question. We support the creation of guidelines to assist medical professionals and institutions in navigating important ethical, legal, and clinical aspects to CO. As no current CO guidelines exist within Spain’s healthcare system, we offer a set of guidelines to provide practical and appropriate application of CO in Spain. Our proposed framework of eligibility prerequisites (performed by the medical professional) and procedural process (performed by the governing institution) ensures that CO can be used in a legally and ethically acceptable manner.

Availability of data and materials

Not applicable.

References

  1. Real Academia Española. Diccionario de la Lengua Española. Year 2019 update. Available at: https://dle.rae.es/objeción+. Accessed 3 Oct 2020.

  2. Couceiro A, Seoane JA, Hernando P. La objeción de conciencia en el ámbito clínico. Propuesta para un uso apropiado (I). Rev Calid Asist. 2011;26(3):188–93.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  3. Herreros B, Moreno-Milán B, Pacho Jiménez E, et al. Terminología en bioética clínica. Rev Med Inst Mex Seguro Soc. 2015;53(6):750–61.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  4. Salas SP, Besio M, BórquezEstefó G, Salinas RA, Valenzuela CY, Micolich C, NovoaSotta F, Bernier Villarroel L, Montt MJ, MisseroniRaddatz A. El médico y la objeción de conciencia: Opinión del Departamento de Ética del Colegio Médico de Chile A. G [Position paper from the Department of Ethics of the Chilean College of Physicians about conscientious objection]. Rev Med Chil. 2016;144(3):382–7. https://0-doi-org.brum.beds.ac.uk/10.4067/S0034-98872016000300015. Spanish. PMID: 27299826; PMCID: PMC7380685.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  5. Gamboa-Antiñolo F-M, Poyato-Galán J-M. La objeción de conciencia de los profesionales sanitarios. Gac Sanit. 2020. Published Online First: 5 February 2004. https://0-doi-org.brum.beds.ac.uk/10.1016/j.gaceta.2020.05.014.

  6. Consejo General De Colegios Oficiales De Médicos. Código Deontológico. 2022. Capítulo VIII, objeción de conciencia. Art. 34-37. Available at: https://www.cgcom.es/sites/main/files/minisite/static/828cd1f8-2109-4fe3-acba-1a778abd89b7/codigo_deontologia. Accessed 9 Jan 2024.

  7. La S-C. objeción de conciencia sanitaria. Derecho y salud. 2010;20(2):49–64.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Gracia D, Rodríguez JJ. Primera parte. Conceptos generales. In: Ética de la objeción de conciencia. Madrid: Fundación de Ciencias de la Salud; 2008. p. 1–10. Available at: https://www.fcs.es/images/Publipdf/Guia_etica_objecion_conciencia.pdf. Accessed 4 Oct 2020.

  9. Fleming V, Frith L, Luyben A, et al. Conscientious objection to participation in abortion by midwives and nurses: a systematic review of reasons. BMC Med Ethics. 2018;19(1):31.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  10. Dobrowolska B, McGonagle I, Pilewska-Kozak A, Kane R. Conscientious object in nursing: regulations and practice in two European countries. Nurs Ethics. 2020;27(1):168–83. https://0-doi-org.brum.beds.ac.uk/10.1177/0969733019845136. Epub 2019 May 21. PMID: 31113265.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  11. Martínez K. Medicina y objeción de conciencia. An Sist Sanit Navar. 2007;30(2):215–23.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  12. Navarro S. Las cosas por su nombre: ¿Objeción de conciencia o desobediencia civil? Rev Bioét Derecho. 2013;28:91–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Biondo F. Subjetivismo ético y objeción de conciencia. Derechos y libertades. 2018. p. 205–228.

  14. Altisent R, Rubio M, Buil B. Objeción de conciencia en la profesión médica: propuesta de validación. Med Clin (Barc). 2011;137(8):366–9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Savulescu J. Conscientious objection in medicine. BMJ. 2006;332:294–7.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  16. Eberl JT. Conscientious objection in health care. Theor Med Bioeth. 2019;40(6):483–6.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  17. Schuklenk U. Conscientious objection in medicine: accommodation versus professionalism and the public good. Br Med Bull. 2018;126(1):47–56.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  18. Lewis-Newby M, Wicclair M, Pope T, Rushton C, Curlin F, Diekema D, Durrer D, Ehlenbach W, Gibson-Scipio W, Glavan B, Langer RL, Manthous C, Rose C, Scardella A, Shanawani H, Siegel MD, Halpern SD, Truog RD, White DB, ATS Ethics and Conflict of Interest Committee. An official American Thoracic Society policy statement: managing conscientious objections in intensive care medicine. Am J Respir Crit Care Med. 2015;191(2):219–27. https://0-doi-org.brum.beds.ac.uk/10.1164/rccm.201410-1916ST. PMID: 25590155.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  19. Gracia D. Objeción de conciencia: las lecciones de un debate. Rev Calid Asist. 2011;26(3):143–5.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  20. Spanish Constitutional Court. Ruling 53/1985, of April 11, 1985. Published in the Official Bulletin of the Spanish State, or “BOE,” number 119, of May 18, 1985. Available at: https://hj.tribunalconstitucional.es/es-ES/Resolucion/Show/433. Accessed 4 Oct 2020.

  21. Organic Law 3/2021 for the Regulation of Euthanasia. Available at: https://www.boe.es/buscar/doc.php?id=BOE-A-2021-4628. Accessed 9 Jan 2024.

  22. Spanish Constitution of 1978. Title I. On fundamental rights and duties. Chapter Two. Rights and freedoms. Section 1.ª On fundamental rights and public freedoms. Article 16.1. Available at: https://www.boe.es/buscar/act.php?id=BOE-A-1978-31229. Accessed 3 Oct 2020.

  23. Spanish Constitutional Court. Sentence nº 15/1982, of April 23, 1982, issued on Appeal nº 205/1981 and published in the Official Bulletin of the Spanish State, or BOE on May 16, 1982. Available at: https://hj.tribunalconstitucional.es/es-ES/Resolucion/Show/57. Accessed 4 Oct 2020.

  24. Spanish Constitutional Court. Ruling 160/87, of October 27, 1987, published in the Official Bulletin of the Spanish State, or BOE, number 271, of November 12, 1987. Available at: http://hj.tribunalconstitucional.es/es-ES/Resolucion/Show/892. Accessed 4 Oct 2020.

  25. Spanish Constitutional Court. Ruling 161/87, of October 27, 1987, published in the Official Bulletin of the Spanish State, or BOE, number 271, of November 12, 1987. Available at: http://hj.tribunalconstitucional.es/es-ES/Resolucion/Show/893. Accessed 4 Oct 2020.

  26. Spanish Public Act 2/2010 on Sexual and Reproductive Health and Voluntary Interruption of Pregnancy. Available at: https://www.boe.es/buscar/act.php?id=BOE-A-2010-3514. Accessed 4 Oct 2020.

  27. La GM. objeción de conciencia del personal sanitario a las instrucciones previas por motivos religiosos. In: Martín I, González M, editors. Algunas cuestiones controvertidas del ejercicio del derecho fundamental de libertad religiosa en España. Madrid: Fundación universitaria española; 2009. p. 275–95.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Organización Colegial de Enfermería. Código Deontológico de Enfermería Española, 1989. Capítulo III, Derechos de los enfermos y profesionales de enfermería. Art. 22. Available at: http://www.ee.lafe.san.gva.es/pdfs/codigodeontologicoesp.pdf. Accessed 5 Oct 2020.

  29. Consejo General de Colegios Oficiales de Farmacéuticos. Código de Ética Farmacéutica y Deontología de la Profesión Farmacéutica, 2018. Capítulo V, de la calidad en la dispensación y otros servicios profesionales. Art. 21.3. Capítulo XII, de la objeción de conciencia. Art. 46–7. Available at: https://www.portalfarma.com/Profesionales/organizacionfcolegial/portal-transparencia/Documents/2018-Codigo-Deontologia-Profesion-Farmaceutica-CGCOF.pdf. Accessed 5 Oct 2020.

  30. Forster M. Ethical position of medical practitioners who refuse to treat unvaccinated children. J Med Ethics. 2019;45(8):552–5.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  31. Bouthillier M-E, Opatrny L. A qualitative study of physicians’ conscientious objections to medical aid in dying. Palliat Med. 2019;33(9):1212–20.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  32. Cowley C. Selective conscientious objection in healthcare. New Bioeth. 2019;25(3):236–47.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  33. Eberl JT. Protecting reasonable conscientious refusals in health care. Theor Med Bioeth. 2019;40:565–81.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  34. Faundes A, Alves G, Duarte MJ. Conscientious objection or fear of social stigma and unawareness of ethical obligations. Int J Gynaecol Obstet. 2013;123Suppl 3:S57-9.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Blackshaw BP, Rodger D. Questionable benefits and unavoidable personal beliefs: defending conscientious objection for abortion. J Med Ethics. 2019;0:1–5.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Savulescu J, Schuklenk U. Doctors have no right to refuse medical assistance in dying, abortion or contraception. Bioethics. 2017;31(3):162–70.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  37. Card RF, Williams KG. Emergency contraception, institutional conscience, and pharmacy practice. J Pharm Pract. 2014;27(2):174–7.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  38. Seroru GI. Ethical issues in human reproduction: Islamic perspectives. Gynecol Endocrinol. 2013;29(11):949–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. Card RF. The inevitability of assessing reasons in debates about conscientious objection in medicine. Camb Q Healthc Ethics. 2017;26(1):82–96.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  40. Magelssen M. Secularity, abortion, assisted dying and the future of conscientious objection: modelling the relationship between attitudes. J Med Ethics. 2017;43:841–4.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  41. Saad TC. Conscientious objection and clinical judgement: the right to refuse to harm. New Bioeth. 2019;25(3):248–61.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  42. Baldelli I, Biolatti B, Santi P, et al. Conscientious objection to animal testing: a preliminary survey among Italian medical and veterinary students. Altern Lab Anim. 2019;47(1):30–8.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  43. Cameron ME. Value, be, do: guidelines for resolving ethical conflict. J Nurs Law. 2000;6(4):15–24.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  44. Miles SH, Gomez CF. The evolution of health protocol practices and objectives. In: Protocols for elective use of life-sustanting treatments. New York: Springer Publishing Company; 1989. p. 3–14.

  45. Veterans Administration Model for DNR Ptotocols, Circular 10-84-179, October 1984. Protocols for elective use of life-sustanting treatments. New York: Springer Publishing Company, 1989. p. 136–143.

  46. Guidelines on long-term life-supporting technology – ventilators and dialysis. In: Guidelines on the termination of life-sustaining and the care of the dying. The Hasting Center. Bloomington: Indiana University Press; 1989. p. 35–42.

  47. Herreros B, Ramnath VR, Bishop L, Pintor E, Martín MD, Sánchez-González MA. Clinical ethics protocols in the clinical ethics committees of Madrid. J Med Ethics. 2014;40(3):205–8.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  48. Parliamentary Assembly (Council of Europe). The right to conscientious objection in lawful medical care. Resolution 1763 (2010). Available at: http://assembly.coe.int/nw/xml/News/FeaturesManager-View-EN.asp?ID=950. Accessed 5 Oct 2020.

  49. García T. La objeción de conciencia. Revista Jurídica de Investigación e Innovación Educativa. 2015;11(1):49–72.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Chavkin W, Leitman L, Polin K. Conscientious objection and refusal to provide reproductive healthcare: a White Paper examining prevalence, health consequences, and policy responses. Int J Gynecol Obstet. 2013;123:S41–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  51. Kogan R, Kraschel KL, Haupt CE. Which legal approaches help limit harms to patients from clinicians’ conscience-based refusals? AMA J Ethics. 2020;22(3):E209-216.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  52. Ameneiros Lago E, Carballada Rico C, Garrido Sanjuán JA. Los documentos de Instrucciones Previas y la planificación anticipada de las decisiones sanitarias. Galicia Clín. 2011;72(3):121–4.

    Google Scholar 

  53. FIGO Committee for the Ethical Aspects of Human Reproduction and Women’s Health. Ethical guidelines on conscientious objection. Reprod Health Matters. 2006;14(27):148–9. https://0-doi-org.brum.beds.ac.uk/10.1016/s0968-8080(06)27223-9. PMID: 16779901.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  54. Shemie SD, Simpson C, Blackmer J, MacDonald S, Dhanani S, Torrance S, Byrne P, Donation Physician Ethics Guide Meeting Participants. Ethics guide recommendations for organ-donation-focused physicians: endorsed by the Canadian Medical Association. Transplantation. 2017;101(5S Suppl 1):S41–7. https://0-doi-org.brum.beds.ac.uk/10.1097/TP.0000000000001694. PMID: 28437370.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  55. Lemiengre J, de Casterlé BD, Van Craen K, Schotsmans P, Gastmans C. Institutional ethics policies on medical end-of-life decisions: a literature review. Health Policy. 2007;83(2–3):131–43. https://0-doi-org.brum.beds.ac.uk/10.1016/j.healthpol.2007.02.013. Epub 2007 Apr 12. PMID: 17433489.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  56. Bioethics Committee of Spain. Opinion of the Bioethics Committee of Spain on conscientious objection in health care. Issued on October 13, 2011. Available at: http://assets.comitedebioetica.es/files/documentacion/es/La%20objecion%20de%20conciencia%20en%20sanidad.pdf. Accessed 6 Oct 2020.

  57. Peiro AM. Objeción de conciencia en el sistema sanitario público. Rev Clin Esp. 2010;6(20):940–3.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Gea-Sánchez M, Terés-Vidal L, Briones-Vozmediano E, et al. Conflictos entre la ética enfermera y la legislación sanitaria en España. Gac Sanit. 2016;30(3):178–83.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Not applicable.

Funding

This research received no specific grant from any funding agency in the public, commercial or not-for-profit sectors.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

PPP: This author has contributed to the conception of the article, has drafted and revised the article. PPP has approved the submitted version and is agree both to be personally accountable for the author’s own contributions and to ensure that questions related to the accuracy or integrity of any part of the work. TRV: This author has contributed to the design of the work and has drafted the article. TRV has approved the submitted version and is agree both to be personally accountable for the author’s own contributions and to ensure that questions related to the accuracy or integrity of any part of the work. VR: This author has revised the article. VR has approved the submitted version and is agree both to be personally accountable for the author’s own contributions and to ensure that questions related to the accuracy or integrity of any part of the work. BH: This author has contributed to the conception and design of the article and has drafted and revised the article. BH has approved the submitted version and is agree both to be personally accountable for the author’s own contributions and to ensure that questions related to the accuracy or integrity of any part of the work. ASS: This author has worked in the design of the guidelines and reviewed and contributed with the drafts of the paper until the final manuscript were approved.

Authors’ information

Not applicable.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Pilar Pinto Pastor.

Ethics declarations

Ethics approval and consent to participate

Not applicable.

Consent for publication

Not applicable.

Competing interests

The authors have no conflicts of interests to disclose.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article's Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article's Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/. The Creative Commons Public Domain Dedication waiver (http://creativecommons.org/publicdomain/zero/1.0/) applies to the data made available in this article, unless otherwise stated in a credit line to the data.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Herreros, B., Ramnath, V.R., Santiago-Saez, A. et al. Guidelines for conscientious objection in Spain: a proposal involving prerequisites and protocolized procedure. Philos Ethics Humanit Med 19, 4 (2024). https://0-doi-org.brum.beds.ac.uk/10.1186/s13010-024-00155-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://0-doi-org.brum.beds.ac.uk/10.1186/s13010-024-00155-x

Keywords